It has been said, so many times, in fact, that it has become almost cliché, that ideas have consequences or, to put it another way, that wrong thought leads to wrong action. In many cases an incorrect line of reasoning immediately leads to obviously incorrect action, however, in some instances an error can go relatively unnoticed, either because the one holding to the idea puts it into practice only erratically or because the belief, although incorrect, produces a correct result in most cases. These errors are, in fact, the most dangerous, since they are rarely seen yet can still lead to incorrect actions.

     One particular such error lies in the common thought the Christians ought to do the right thing because doing so creates good results. It would seem to be apparently logical to base one's judgment of what the right action is on whether or not the results it produces are desirable. Some may already recognize the insidious error found in this line of reasoning, but it is certainly not readily apparent to most people. The fact is, the statement that a Christian should base his judgment of an action on the results the action produces is the farthest thing from the truth. One could hardly conceive of a more dangerous error for a Christian to hold to. It usually causes the one holding it to arrive at the correct course of action – God's ways are indeed good ways, so in most cases the right action will produce a desirable outcome – but it is most emphatically not a sound basis for any Christian to take action.

     In fact, this “results-based” morality is the product of a secular humanist philosophy, not Christianity. Given no other standard to judge behavior humanist philosophers have devised a number of devices for judging the ethics of an action, all of them based on the results an action achieves. For example, one of the more well-known examples of a non-Christian code of ethics, utilitarianism, argues that the individual should seek to do the greatest possible good for the greatest possible number of people. In other words, the individual should seek the best possible result, where the goodness or badness of the result is defined based on the net “good” (which can only be defined as pleasure without some other standard to define good) the action produces. Other codes of ethics may define what result is desirable differently, but the basic principle is the same: we take action in order to achieve a desirable result and for no other reason.

     The discussion in the above paragraph should begin to give the reader an idea of at least one of the salient flaws of results-based morality. By basing its judgment of the rightness or wrongness of an action on the results achieved, it ignores the fact that the full results of an action cannot be entirely known even after the action has been taken. Christianity, which assumes absolute right and wrong, at the very least strongly suggests that it is possible to know whether an action is right or wrong before the action is taken, and certainly, failing that, afterward. However, if we base our determination of right and wrong on the results of the action we must inevitably conclude that it is impossible to know whether an action is right or wrong before the action is made, and only possible to guess afterward. This fact alone should strongly suggest that Christianity and results-based morality are incompatible.

     If this was not enough, results-based morality also misplaces the burden of responsibility for effecting change in the world. Any Christian should recognize that not only does predicting and effecting positive change in the future exceed our ability, it exceeds our responsibility as well. God is more than capable of achieving any results he desires, whatever our action, while our inability to predict future results inevitably requires an inability to consistently achieve our desired results. We are like children, assigned a task by our elder, not because he requires our assistance for the task but out of kindness towards us. Our “goodness” is therefore not judged by the success of our bumbling, amateurish actions – had that been the point the adult could have done it himself far better – but by the fact that we tried to follow the directions given to us. Similarly, we take action not to align world events with God's will – he is more than capable of doing that without our aid – but to align ourselves with God's will. What happens is incidental to the single most important point of any action: how closely it conforms with God's standard of holiness.

     With this in mind Christians must emphatically reject attempts to judge the morality of an action based on subjective determinations of whether the result achieved was “good” or “bad.” Such a determination assumes more responsibility and more ability than humans have or were ever intended to have. Instead, we must embrace the belief that the morality of every action is decided solely by how closely that action conforms with God's standard. In many cases actions that conform to God's standard will produce what we view as “good” results, but that is never why an action is right, merely a sign that it may be. Accepting a correct view of morality requires not only that Christians understand such a correct view of morality, but also that they apply it. We must check ourselves when we find ourselves explaining that we are taking an action because it results in certain desirable things and instead teach ourselves to link each action to specific Biblical principles that support it. By doing otherwise we risk allowing an apparently trivial yet still dangerous error to compromise our modes of thinking and acting, potentially causing us to take wrong action, something that should be anathema to the careful Christian.

     Nuclear power today is defined by the antiquated needs of, of all things, submarines. During the development of the USS Nautilus, the first nuclear submarine, it became apparent that a solid uranium-fueled reactor would not only provide certain benefits when used in a submarine, it could also produce weaponizable byproducts, and, perhaps most important, could be ready sooner than its many competitors. Admiral Hyman Rickover decided in favor of a water cooled solid reactor fueled by uranium oxide enriched in U-235., and in doing so decided the future of nuclear power.

     To modern eyes Rickover's choice seems inexplicable. Up until his decision thorium appeared to be the future of nuclear power, however, once the water cooled solid uranium reactor was supported by the deep pockets of Uncle Sam, the contest was essentially over. Thorium, although promising, required development and could not compete with uranium. Although the reasons behind Rickover's choice are no longer relevant, uranium has maintained its ascendancy due to the massive costs associated with building and operating a nuclear reactor.

     The advantages of a thorium-fueled reactor seem almost too good to be true. Thorium is approximately four times as abundant as uranium, a much higher percentage of the energy inherent in that supply can be extracted, and it is often found in conjunction with, and can easily be separated from, the vitally important rare earth elements, making it an attractive long-term option. In an age when the dangers of nuclear proliferation are glaringly obvious, one feature of thorium which to Admiral Rickover was a negative, has become one of its most highly touted selling points: a liquid fluoride thorium reactor (LFTR) of the sort proposed by most of the thorium lobby does not produce weaponizable byproducts (Hargraves and Moir 2010). An LFTR produces energy, freshwater, and a very small amount of low-grade waste. Due to this fact it could be installed in places a conventional uranium reactor could not, removing the opportunity for endless foreign policy debates about whether a particular partially unhinged petty dictator is pursuing nuclear power for peaceful or military reasons.

     Thorium's case is further advanced by the nature and amount of the waste produced. An LFTR produces less than 10% of the waste a conventional reactor does, and waste from an LFTR has less than 1% of the radiotoxicity of waste from a conventional nuclear reactor. Further, that waste, rather than taking on the order of ten thousand years to become safe, it requires closer to one hundred years to become safe. These advantages are due to the fact that most of the waste produced by an LFTR is reused in the reactor, leaving only a small, relatively innocuous portion to be disposed of.

     Once an LFTR has been built, thorium can also be more than competitive economically. At present electricity in the United States costs between $0.05 and $0.06 per kWh and the potential “clean” energy sources—wind and solar—cost between $0.20 and $0.30 per kWh. In contrast, an LFTR has the potential to produce power at a cost as low as $0.03 per kWh (Hargraves and Moir 2010). The difference per kWh is small, but when one considers that, given that the average home consumes around 10,000 kWh per year, an LFTR could mean the difference between an annual electric bill of $50,000 or $60,000 at current rates and a bill of only $30,000 it suddenly becomes much more meaningful.

     In light of the devastating effects of mismanaged nuclear power at Chernobyl, Three Mile Island, and, more recently, Fukushima, few care about the logistics and viability of a power source if it also carries the potential to irradiate the surrounding countryside. Here thorium continues to shine. A conventional reactor is cooled by pressurized water, creating the potential for a catastrophic leak. Further, when the temperature in a conventional reactor rises the fuel expands, which accelerates the reaction, which heats the reactor, which in turn causes the fuel to expand. A conventional reactor aslo requires active cooling, meaning that if power is shut down such that cooling can no longer take place, as occurred at Fukushima, the reaction will continue to accelerate until the reactor melts down. An LFTR is cooled molten fluoride salt which is not under pressure, removing the single most dangerous feature of conventional reactors. Additionally, an LFTR will simply shut down if power is removed—unlike a conventional reactor, it does not require power to shut down but to stay running (Hargraves and Moir 2010; Shiga 2011). The LFTR thus presents an extremely attractive option as far as safety is concerned.

     Thorium presents an economical, safe, effective, and “clean” energy source. It can compete with and beat coal and oil in cost. It can be used in areas too unstable to sustain conventional nuclear and too poor or incompetent to use other conventional fuel sources. It's waste products are not abundant and are relatively innocuous. Although mining and transportation may be accompanied by some pollutant emissions, the reactor itself is not. Why, then, is thorium still an unknown cousin of uranium? The answer, as one might expect, is money and government. A prototype thorium reactor would cost on the order of $1 billion dollars; a commercial model closer to $5 to $10 billion. Very few people are willing to spend that kind of money on a project which is, whatever its potential, still unproven. Further, any investment of that magnitude would have yield a significant return within a reasonable amount of time. At best, it would take 10 years for an investor to being to see returns on the investment and, crucially, the extent and even the existence of those returns hinges on an uncertain regulatory environment. In countries where the government has demonstrated that it is willing to support investment in thorium research projects to build thorium-fueled reactors have moved ahead. In countries where the government has not shown such resolve thorium research has stalled or has never begun. In any case, it is hard to believe that the obvious benefits of thorium will remain hidden for long: it seems far more likely that in thorium we can see what will one day be unequivocally the fuel of the future.


References:

Hargraves, Robert, and Ralph Moir. 2010. "Liquid Fluoride Thorium Reactors." American Scientist 98, no. 
     4: 304-313.
Shiga, David. 2011. "Rescuing Nuclear Power." New Scientist 209, no. 2805: 8-10.


     The world has no shortage of well-intentioned individuals who loudly condemn what they view as the intolerance of religion, decrying and renouncing all forms of religion. However, in their refusal to tolerate intolerance they themselves engage in intolerance. These eidolons of universal tolerance insist on tolerance for some things and intolerance for others. Although these crusaders are loath to admit it, just as those they condemn choose which actions will be tolerated and which will not, they must choose which intolerance is condemned and which is not. This in itself is not a problem—every one of us every day makes decisions about what is right and what is wrong, and none of us give it a second thought.

     A difficult problem arises, however, when one examines the basis of this refusal to tolerate certain forms of intolerance. On the surface, these crusaders will boldly proclaim “right” and “wrong,” citing examples and lauding the former while condemning the later. When pressed. the definitions become much less clear. Prominent atheist and Harvard Law professor (although in the modern era one could argue that the two descriptors are synonymous) Alan Dershowitz admitted that he didn't know what was right. He claimed to be able to discern wrong, but what basis he could use for his discernment is unclear. It is likely that his basis for determining wrong is the same as that for determining right among those divorced from ultimate reality, that is, no basis but the preference of the individual. In reality, the issue is a matter of preference on the part of the speaker. One must choose which forms of intolerance to refuse to tolerate—after all, the decision not to tolerate anything is intolerant by its nature—and that decision, in the absence of the teachings of intolerant religion, must be based on the whims of the one making the decision, not on eternal principles. A decision made on such a basis has no authority for anyone but the one making it—it should have no more weight for listeners than a statement about the speakers preference in food, movies, or interior decorating. At a societal level, as these principles are being applied, right and wrong are thus determined by many personal preferences taken as an aggregate—in short, majority vote. No one in his right mind, after viewing the catalog of past horrendous actions that seemed right to the majority at the time but now seem so glaringly wrong, could argue that this is any basis for morality.

     Without a basis for morality besides “I like it” or “I don't like it” (whatever rubric one uses, whether Kantianism, Utilitarianism, or any other ethical standard based in human reason, it is, at its heart, only preference) what is left for establishing a code of conduct for society is nothing but the simplistic “because I say so” from the majority. What is so thoroughly despised in our parents some would have us accept as the sole basis for laws and government. This philosophy cannot allow any rights outside of those recognized by the preference of the majority. If there is no higher authority than will of the majority in a very real sense rights are granted, not by the creator or another higher authority who society ought to recognize, but by society itself. One could argue, then, that in the 1850's a black man, as Chief Justice Taney stated, had no rights that society was bound to respect because society did not choose to grant those rights to him. Similarly, a Jew in Nazi Germany would not have any rights other than those granted by society around him—and society, as was so tragically demonstrated, chose to grant very, very few. Today society in the United States grants no rights to the unborn, and one can only imagine which group will be next.

     A society cannot exist with this as its standard for law and government. Those who advocate for refusing to tolerate what they define as intolerance in reality enforce a form of intellectual tyranny just as oppressive within its sphere as any concocted by history's infamous tyrants and dictators. Indeed, because this standard of right and wrong is based in nothing more than the whim of the individual yet held with as much adamant fervor as any religious belief it establishes a precedent that could be used for horrendous oppression. In the name of tolerance they have assaulted the foundations of freedom in America. By establishing the idea that rights are based not on changeless principles but on the whim of society, and by beating those who step outside of the rights society chooses to grant back into line, they instead lay a foundation for future tyranny.  

     1973 brought a lot of things to America. That year we pulled out of Vietnam, leaving our South Vietnamese allies to face the Russian-backed North alone. Richard Nixon assured the country that he was not a crook. The World Trade Center became the tallest building in the world. The nerdier among us may mark it as the year Skylab, our first space station, was launched. Nothing that happened that year, however, had a greater impact than the Supreme Court's ruling in Roe v. Wade on January 22 that abortion was a constitutionally protected right. With that ruling state laws across the country banning abortion were struck down, fundamentally changing the nation.

     The Supreme Court's decision wasn't the first salvo on the topic of abortion. Efforts to relax state laws prohibiting abortion to include exceptions for rape, incest, the life of the mother, and other extreme cases through legislative means had been going on for years. No one, though, had argued that abortion was a constitutionally protected right. Justice Blackmun, together with his liberal colleagues, argued that a right to privacy existed in the Constitution, based either in the fourteenth or the ninth amendment, and that that right to privacy justified aborting unborn children up until the child would be viable if delivered. The decision led to more than fifty-two million abortions in the subsequent years—for comparison, total American deaths in World War II only come out to about one million.

     The decision in Roe v. Wade is troubling for a number of issues, some of them not even related to abortion. First, the court found a right to privacy in the Constitution not recognized by any scholar of that document. Certainly the Supreme Court, beginning in 1923, had actively reinterpreted the Constitution to extend the right to liberty found in the fourteenth amendment into a general right to privacy, but the 1973 decision expanded that effort massively. Chief Justice Douglas in Griswold v. Connecticut had found a right to privacy in the “emanations” and “penumbras” of other rights actually found in the Constitution. The district court that ruled in Roe v. Wade prior to the Supreme Court found that the right to privacy was derived from the ninth amendment. Justice Blackmun, in writing his opinion in Roe v. Wade expanded that right to privacy drastically and gave it a home in the fourteenth amendment.

     Each possible source of a constitutional right to privacy, however, lacks substance. The argument from “emanations” and “penumbras” is a fairly obvious attempt to read something into the Constitution the founders' did not intend. The argument from the ninth amendment is also badly off the mark. The Constitution is a limit on national, not state, government. The fact that the Constitution does not “deny or disparage” rights not specifically protected does not in any way mean that the states cannot do so. If one were to make the argument that the ninth amendment limits the states no state could pass any law that limits the rights of any individual in any way, since all rights would be protected by the ninth amendment. This is obviously absurd. The argument from the fourteenth amendment is also flawed. Although the fourteenth amendment guarantees that no state can deprive any citizen of “life, liberty, or property without due process of law,” the wording clearly intends “life, liberty, or property” to mean the three forms of punishment possible: death, imprisonment, or fine. Once again, by making the argument that liberty is intended to apply to all forms of liberty one reaches an entirely untenable conclusion.

     A greater flaw in the decision's reasoning lies in the age when the unborn child begins to be partially protected. According to the decision states cannot limit abortion in any way except to protect the life of the mother until the baby would be viable if delivered. The obvious implication is that life begins at viability. This lacks even basic common sense. While the decision, based on the ability of the medical community at that time, placed the line when viability began at twenty-eight weeks today fifty to seventy percent of babies born at twenty-four weeks survive. Even at twenty-three weeks thirty-five percent survive. Basing one's definition of what life should be protected on the viability of the child outside the womb thus places life entirely at the hands of technology. Fifty years ago keeping a child born at twenty-three weeks gestation alive would have been unimaginable. Today, although difficult, it is possible. One can imagine that similar advances will occur in the next fifty years, meaning that children who, according to Roe v. Wade, could not be protected by state law now would present little problem to the medical professionals of that time. To emphasis the absurdity of viability as a measure of the beginning of protected life a thought experiment could be useful. Imagine that a device capable of maintaining fetal viability beginning at fifteen weeks gestation was invented. The inventor, being a particularly greedy fellow, refused to reveal the plans or how the complex machine could be used before he was paid. Without a demonstration no company would pay for the eccentric genius's machine, so he died without revealing the secret of his invention. Now, are the unborn children at fifteen, sixteen, seventeen, etc. weeks gestation alive in such a way that they should be protected? Should they be allowed to be protected by state law? After all, the equipment does exist to keep them alive outside the womb. On the other hand, no one is capable of actually using the equipment, so perhaps they shouldn't be protected. One could go on and imagine any number of situations in which fetal viability would be completely inadequate to mark the beginning of life.

     This example, along with other objections to fetal viability as a measure of the beginning of protected life, merely highlights the problem: fetal viability has absolutely no relation to life. Arguing that an unborn child is not alive because it would not be viable outside the womb is exactly equivalent to arguing that you are not alive because you would not be viable if a maniac slammed an icepick through your head. One's future or potential state cannot, by definition, affect one's present state.

     A simple rule of thumb is that if something is not considered to be characteristic of human life in adult humans it should not be considered to be the single mark of life in the unborn. That means that, since future and potential viability are not considered to be marks of humanity in the population at large, they should not be considered such in the unborn. Further, no one seriously believes that the ability to feel pain, cognizance, appearance, or the size of one's brain or other organs marks human life in the population at large, so it should not be the mark of life in the unborn. In reality, the one physical trait that is universally considered to mark a human being is the presence of a unique set of DNA. One cannot point to any other stage in the development of an unborn human when anything intrinsic to the nature of the child changes dramatically enough to warrant being considered to be the beginning of life.

     Given that life logically must begin at conception, when all the information necessary for life is present, society, through government, has not only the right but also the duty to protect that right. First and foremost among government's tasks is the duty to protect life and implicit in that duty is the necessity of first defining life by the best means possible. Thus abortion is not, as many would have us believe, a private, personal choice beyond the reach of government intervention, it is, as we have seen, an attack on the most defenseless among us and as such is well within the purview of government. Even liberal Justice Blackmun admitted that if the unborn baby was a person it would “of course” be protected by the fourteenth amendment. This means that the unborn are protected by the fourteenth amendment's guarantee of equal protection of the laws, and Congress is authorized to pass appropriate legislation to enforce that protection. It is past high time that Congress and the American people shake off the Supreme Court's deadly foolishness by taking appropriate action to protect the rights of every person within the United States, born or unborn.

     In the wake of the high profile shootings this year in Colorado, Oregon, and Connecticut several prominent public figures, notably New York Mayor Michael Bloomberg, have claimed that stricter gun control could have solved the problem. These avid supporters of further government regulation of firearms argue that the provisions of the second amendment should be set aside in the interests of public safety. After all, some action must be taken to prevent further tragedies of this nature, and current gun laws obviously have not achieved the desired success. This view may sound reasonable, but in reality it is simplistic and ignores vital aspects of the situation.

     In fact, laws restricting citizens' ability to carry guns create an environment ripe for exactly the kind of tragedy that occurred in Colorado. Rather than being an argument for further gun control, the shooting is an indictment of current gun control laws. The theater in which the shooting occurred, owned by Cinemark Century Theaters, was officially a gun-free zone, as are all of Cinemark's theaters. The mall in Oregon was, like most malls across the country, a gun free zone and, obviously, Sandy Hook Elementary School was a gun free zone, as are most schools and universities. With these shootings more than 75% of mass public shootings since 1999, have occurred in gun free zones. That includes 77% of fatalities since 1999 and 83% of all those shot in mass public shootings since 1999. Far from filling their intended purpose as a safe area where students and others could pursue their lives free from the threat of gun violence, gun-free zones make an appealing target for lunatics across the country. This provides strong support for gun rights advocates' contention that more guns means less crime.

     Many respond by pointing to the fact that America has the highest rate of gun ownership of any nation on earth and has very high rates of gun related homicides (in the top ten worldwide). They argue that the link is clear: Americans have more guns, therefore Americans commit more crimes. The reality is far more complex. Although it is true that America does have higher rates of gun related homicide, it also has higher rates of homicides completely unrelated to firearm use. Americans simply commit more murders (which is partially a result of the fact that the United States groups both criminal homicides and justifiable homicides, creating an inflated number). Further, Switzerland, which requires gun ownership for all adult males and has the highest rate of firearm ownership of any developed country besides the United States, has one of the lowest rates of gun related crime and has the fourth lowest homicide rate overall. Obviously the presence or absence of guns is not the primary indicator of homicide rates (or indeed of the rate of occurrence of any crime except, possibly, sexual assault).

     This fact is seen in the lack of a statistical connection between a population's ability to own guns and low rates of gun crimes. According to the United Nations Office on Gun and Crimes (2000), the top five developed countries in per capita rates of homicides are, in order of decreasing homicide rates, Estonia, Belarus, Ukraine, Barbados, and Poland. Of these Estonia, Belarus, and Barbados prohibit gun ownership entirely while Ukraine and Poland allow regulated gun ownership. No correlation is apparent in this data, a trait shared by the five countries with lowest total homicide rate. These, Hong Kong, Singapore, Switzerland, Denmark, and Ireland, are also split, with Hong Kong and Singapore prohibiting all guns and the rest allowing (Switzerland even requires) gun ownership. Further, the top five developed countries in homicide rate with firearms is similarly divided. This group, again listed in descending order of homicides, is composed of Belarus, Barbados, the United States, Slovakia, and Estonia. Belarus, Barbados, and Estonia prohibit gun ownership while the United States and Slovakia do not. Similarly, the five developed countries with the lowest rates of homicide with firearms, Hong Kong, Singapore, England and Wales, New Zealand, and Spain, are equally split, with Hong Kong and Singapore prohibiting gun ownership entirely and England and Wales, New Zealand, and Spain allowing regulated gun ownership. The same statistical trend, or more accurately, lack of a statistical trend, occurs in all other lists of homicide rates by country. This fact is telling. Not only is total homicide rate independent of the legality or illegality of firearms, the rate of homicides committed with firearms isn't even dependent on the legality or illegality of firearms. In some cases banning guns may decrease the rate of homicides with firearms and thus the total homicide rate, in others it may not. Obviously other factors besides guns are far more important here.

     Less drastic attempts to limit gun ownership, for example, banning certain types of firearms, has shown itself, at best, no more effective than banning guns entirely: that is, not at all effective. In 1982 Chicago instituted a policy banning handguns outright in the city. That year approximately 45% of homicides in the city were committed with handguns. Since that time the overall murder rate in Chicago has averaged 17% lower. Unfortunately for proponents of gun control, the nationwide murder rate has averaged 25% lower and the percentage of homicides committed with handguns has risen steadily since the ban until in 2008 96% of homicides in Chicago were committed with handguns. It is patently obvious that the ban didn't work at all as intended.

     It is possible, however, that Chicago was simply an example of poor enforcement. Britain also instituted a crackdown on guns in 1968 and 1997. The 1968 law required anyone purchasing any firearm to obtain a certificate from their district police chief. Obtaining this certificate involved the payment of a fee and convincing the district police chief that they had a good reason for purchasing a firearm, and were not a threat to society. The 1968 law also required that the certificates specify the identification number of the firearm. In 1997 Britain passed a law banning handguns, and, using the identification numbers provided by the 1968 law, confiscated almost every gun in the country. Since the passage of the 1968 law the homicide rate has averaged 52% higher, while since the passage of the 1997 law the homicide rate has averaged 15% higher.

     Britain's stunning lack of success was matched, however, by a similar utter failure in the United States. A law banning handguns in Washington D.C. was passed in 1976. After the passage of this law the homicide rate in Washington D.C. average 72% higher than previously. The law was struck down by the U.S. Supreme Court in 2008 and homicide rates appear to be returning to pre-1976 levels. In short, laws restricting the sale, ownership, or use of firearms appear to, at best, merely maintain existing homicide rates. At worst they can have a severely negative effect on homicide rates.

     Even the few cases cited as successes by advocates of gun control are hardly appealing. Australia has been mentioned in several articles on the subject as an excellent example of the positive effects of gun control. In 1996, in the wake of a tragic mass public shooting, Australia enacted a buyback program together with extensive regulations which guns are legal and which are not. Supporters of the legislation proudly point to the fact that no mass public shootings have occurred since that time, along with a slight decrease in overall gun violence, as evidence that the legislation worked. They ignore several troubling facts, however. Since the passage of the 1996 law 87% of gun crimes have been committed with illegal firearms. As opponents of gun control have argued, criminals will still find a way to get guns, if perhaps still in lower numbers. The other side of the story is unequivocally negative. The overall crime rate rose dramatically. Australia is now third in per capita rapes and sexual assaults and second among developed countries. The only developed country ahead of it in that category is South Africa, which also has quite restrictive gun control laws. The phenomenon is not limited to Australia and South Africa. Throughout the world rates of rape and sexual assault tend to rise when gun ownership is limited. Take, for example, U.S. college campuses, which are typically gun-free zones. Several studies estimate that as many as one in four female college students have been sexually assaulted.The negative effects of gun control on violent crime as a whole are abundantly evident in Mexico, where gun laws have historically been far more restrictive than those in the United States yet homicide rates are almost three times higher than in its northern neighbor.

     One could list other examples, but the point has been made: at best, gun control maintains the status quo in crime rates. In a worst case scenario it can dramatically influence crime rates upwards. The inevitable conclusion is that an armed populace provides a significant deterrent to those who might desire to commit crime. Rather than providing a pool of armed criminals, arming the populace decreases the number of potential targets for criminals. However well-meaning attempts to limit or prohibit gun ownership may be, they are woefully misguided and potentially dangerous.


Sources:

  1. Agresti, James D. and Reid K. Smith. "Gun Control Facts" Just Facts, September 13, 2010. Revised 12/10/12. http://justfacts.com/guncontrol.asp
  2. “Murders (per capita; most recent) by country,” NationMaster.com, accessed July 17, 2012, http://www.nationmaster.com/graph/cri_mur_percap-crime-murders-per-capita
  3. “Rapes (per capita; most recent) by country,” NationMaster.com, accessed July 10, 2012, http://www.nationmaster.com/graph/cri_rap_percap-crime-rapes-per-capita
  4. “Murders with firearms (most recent) by country,” NationMaster.com, accessed July 22, 2012, http://www.nationmaster.com/graph/cri_mur_wit_fir-crime-murders-with-firearms

     Recently some voices have taken to howling in disgust at the very idea that some parents might homeschool their children. Proponents of our spectacularly unsuccessful school system argue that parents aren't just unqualified, they don't even care enough to educate their children. They paint horrific pictures of children graduating from their homeschool barely being able to read, along with other frightening things, such as children being taught—horror of horrors—the Bible as part of their daily schooling.

     This fear and loathing of homeschooling is nothing new. I have heard a philosophy professor I know proclaim in class that, obviously, no one could object to mandatory public education. Homeschooling has faced fierce opposition since its reemergence in the U.S. in the '70s, '80s, and into the '90s. This, however, was not how things were intended to be. America's founders did discuss the idea of compulsory education, but they rejected it with little debate. The fact is, it is a relatively modern idea that hirelings could even come close to the level of education parents could provide, coming to the U.S. in the 1850s by way of Massachusetts.

     How has our distinctively modern education system turned out? Many have noted that U.S. students are falling behind the rest of the world rapidly, particularly in science and math. This education gap is beginning to affect geopolitical situation. Countries like China and Japan, that have not experienced the same decline in science education that America has, have started to challenge and even overtake the U.S. economically. Teachers scream that the problem lies in funding, that if they were only given more money they could make it work. Unfortunately, the solution does not lie in something as simple as throwing money at the problem. We spend about as much per year on education as the next seven biggest spending countries combined. Accounting for the number of students involved, currently the U.S. spends about $7,743 per student per year. The United Kingdom sits in second at $5,834, Australia takes third with $5,766, Canada spends $5,749, and Finland rounds out the top five with $5,653. In other words, we spend a lot more per student than anyone else (133% of what the runner-up spends per student) and we produce a lesser product. In fact, there is little correlation between expenditures per student and test scores and literacy rates. Countries like Sweden, which ranks fifth in money spent per student, ranks first in literacy rates, first in math test scores, and first in science test scores, jump over the bigger spenders. Even Russia has a higher literacy rate that the U.S.! More money simply will not fix the problem.

     The problem is deeply ingrained in the system itself. In the past homeschooling and similar methods were recognized as the best way to produce intelligent, well-educated people. The shift to government education was not based on quality of education, but ideology. In the U.S., public education was intended to meld immigrants into American culture. Above all else, including quality of education, it was to produce a uniform product—uniformly good, it was hoped, but uniform in any case. Nor has public education as a form of indoctrination been limited to the U.S.. Hitler and the Nazis in Germany made public schooling mandatory and cracked down on parents who attempted to educate their children at home. Hitler even went so far as to say “When an opponent declares, 'I will not come over to your side,' I calmly say, 'Your child belongs to us already... What are you? You will pass on. Your descendants, however, now stand in the new camp. In a short time they will know nothing else but this new community.'” His laws requiring public schooling were explicitly ideological in nature, an overt recognition that the hand that rocks the cradle, as the saying goes, rules the world.

     All of this, however, does nothing to meet the new objections to homeschooling: that it cannot possibly provide the kind of education that the trained professionals in the public education system do. After all, homeschoolers spend on average, according to the most reliable estimates, only $500 per student per year (and I know from personal experience that it can be done for much, much less). How can underfunded and overworked parents provide a better education than well trained teachers with the massive well of deficit spending behind them? To put it bluntly, I have no idea—but they do. Homeschoolers score, on average, 30-40 percentage points higher on standardized tests than public and private schooled students. That number is nothing less than stunning. Parents, spending less than 10% what the government does, not only beat government and private schools, they beat them by an enormous margin. In a country plunging further and further into debt, this is the ultimate example of doing more with less. It is simply the best form of education, bar none.

     So why do some still oppose it? Perhaps they are uniformed or unintelligent—one can never go too far wrong crediting a population with a large degree of stupidity. Remember, though, that in the past very few have supported public education to provide a better educational product. Instead, the goal has been to eliminate an unfortunate minority, one that the majority, or at least those in power, wishes would go away. Only time will tell whether the goal of those advocating public education here in America is the same.

Despicable

     Recent events have brought into the public eye—or rather, back into the public eye—aspects of politicians' lives which have, for much of American history, been intensely personal. In particular, Newt Gingrich, the thrice married former speaker of the house, has been questioned on his past infidelities. He, and his supporters, argue that a politician's personal life will not affect his public policy, even going so far as to label those who would bring up his actions "despicable." This, however, is far from the truth. When one begins to examine the issue in greater detail one is faced with the overwhelming truth that character does matter, and it matters a great deal.

     Certainly one could arrive at a very similar conclusion merely by applying common sense to the issue. Nowhere in life do we see an occasion where someone with no character is able to behave in a moral, principled manner on a consistent basis. When it comes to character, the “truth will out.” Still, it would be pleasant to know that our common sense has not strayed from reality. History shows that it most assuredly has not.

     Warren Harding was the first president known to have had an affair while in office. He had one child by his mistress, Nan Britton, and had several other affairs. The affairs were not common knowledge (the pre-Watergate press really didn't delve deeply into that sort of thing) but they demonstrated a lack of character that showed itself beyond Harding's personal life. His administration was plagued by scandal, and indeed he died just in time to avoid facing some of the consequences of his actions. Further, while in office he held poker parties at which he entertained his guests with bootleg liquor during the height of prohibition, often using whiskey only recently confiscated, and flagrantly ignoring the Constitution he had taken an oath to defend. Harding's shortcomings don't end there, but the incredible failings of those who followed him dwarf his.

     The next four can be grouped together since I doubt very much any of you hold any illusions about their character, making it superfluous to go into great detail about their failings: Franklin Roosevelt, John Kennedy, Lyndon Johnson, and, of course, Bill Clinton. The first on that list brought us social security and ran roughshod over the constitution on a regular basis, exacerbating and lengthening the Great Depression on a massive scale. Kennedy weakened America's place in the world and escalated the U.S. presence in Vietnam without providing a clear goal, setting us up for massive casualties and, eventually, retreat. Johnson brought us almost all of the rest of our current unsustainable wellfare programs and only worsened the situation in Vietnam (not to mention possibly assassinating his predeccesor--but that's a story for another day). And Clinton—well, I think you know quite enough, likely more than enough, about him.

     To simplify the issue, remember this: every American president, to a man, who we have good evidence had an affair while in office has been a disastrous, stunning failure. In fact, the argument for worst president in American history would likely settle around that final group of four. Why would we think that a man who initiated divorce proceedings against one wife while she was hospitalized with cancer and divorced his second only after proposing to his third could possibly break the trend? That is unequivocally despicable and shows a lack of character second to none in modern American politics. Forgiveness is a wonderful thing, but forgiving and forgetting are two completely different things. To forgive is Christlike; to forget completely in a case like this, when the future of our country is on the line, is nothing short of foolish. It is not despicable, then, to mention a candidates infidelities, on the contrary, it is despicable not to.

Motley CREW

     In 2006 the self described watchdog group Citizens for Responsibility and Ethics in Washington (CREW), headed by former Democratic congressional staffer Melanie Sloan, named presidential candidate Rick Santorum on its list of the twenty most corrupt congressmen. CREW is a notoriously partisan group, however, as a look into the other members of congress named in 2006 will tell. First, CREW named twenty members of congress to its list, with five “dishonorable mentions.” Of those twenty-five, twenty-one were Republicans, including numerous Republicans who were running for reelection in hotly contested races, as Rick Santorum was. Now it's just possible that in 2006 84% of the most corrupt members of congress were Republicans, but any thinking person can see it's extremely unlikely. To understand why, then, these particular members of congress were named it would behoove us to look in more detail into each individual case.
     Since Santorum was a senator in 2006, it is most efficient to look first at the senators (there were also only three senators named compared with seventeen representatives, thus it's a much smaller job).

Senator Conrad Burns (R-MT):

     Conrad Burns was elected in 1989 and served until 2007. He was only the second Republican senator from Montana since 1913, and the longest serving to date. During his time in office he served on the Senate Appropriations Committee and was the chair of its Subcommittee on the Interior. He also sat on the Senate Commerce, Science, and Transportation Committee and chaired its Communications Subcommittee. Burns was a strong conservative, although he had a tendency to make unfortunate comments. For his entire career Burns received an NARAL Pro-Choice America rating of 0% and a NRL rating of 100%. This trend continues throughout many other issues. Many other liberal groups give him a poor rating (none rate him higher than 10%, with the exception the AFL-CIO's somewhat anomalous 29%) and conservative groups rate him highly.
     Burns was reelected numerous times, but by 2006 had begun to fall in the polls. At the time CREW released its report Burns was struggling, with a very low approval rating. After Burns connection to Abramoff was publicized by CREW and others, his approval rating fell even more, perhaps, according to some polling services, as low as 39%—the lowest for any sitting senator.

     CREW alleged that Burns funneled money for schools on Indian reservations to the Saginaw Chippewa Tribe, a client of disgraced lobbyist Jack Abramoff. According to CREW's report, Burns on two occasions joined with Democrat senators to request that funding be given to the Saginaw Chippewa Tribe. CREW further alleged that Burns received close to $150,000 between 2004 and 2006 from Abramoff and his clients and associates, including the Saginaw Chippewa Tribe. Burns subsequently returned these donations.
     CREW also claimed that a trip that some of Burns's staffers took to the Super Bowl, paid for by Jack Abramoff, was unethical, although Burns did not violate any senate rules and there is no evidence he even knew of the trip—CREW as much as admitted both of these facts in asking the senate to censure Burns without citing rules violations.
     Beyond the two major issues mentioned, CREW went on to indicate what they saw as unethical behavior in many other, smaller, areas, including his defense of land rights against supporters of wild burros and horses. Unfortunately for CREW, in 2008 the Justice Department cleared Burns of the charges and removed him from their investigation. Nothing indicates that the donations Burns received were in payment for any action on his part, at least to his knowledge, and there is also no evidence that the trip to the Super Bowl was planned or executed with Burns knowledge.

Senator Bill Frist (R-TN):

      Bill Frist is a physician, board-licensed in both general and thoracic surgery. He was elected to the senate in 1995 and served until 2007. During his time in congress he served as the senate majority leader from 2003 to 2007, succeeding Trent Lott. Frist gained prominence when, after two police officers were shot in capitol, he, as the closest doctor, provided medical attention to the officers and the gunman. As a medical doctor who opposed Terri Schiavo's husband's decision to remove her feeding tubes, thus allowing her to die from lack of food and water, Frist came under heavy attack from the left. Frist also stood with Rick Santorum in advancing the Partial Birth Abortion Act of 2003 and opposed exceptions for the life of the mother, since he considered abortion to be hazardous to a woman's health itself. Frist, like Burns, was rated poorly by liberal groups and highly by conservative ones.

     Frist promised not to run for election after his second term, and in 2006 he kept that promise, instead throwing his support to Bob Corker, who defeated his Democrat challenger.

     CREW claimed that Frist had taken out a $1.44 million loan in the name of his 1994 and 2000 campaigns to repay himself $1.2 million which he had lent to his 1994 campaign but had not been repaid. Until this point the entire matter had remained completely above board. However, in its FEC disclosure forms Frist's 2000 campaign failed to report the only—the only campaign that reported it was his by that time dormant 1994 campaign.
     CREW also attacked Frist for insider trading. Frist held, along with his wife and children, a significant amount of stock in HCA, Inc., the family company. In June 2005 Frist sold all of his, his wife's, and his children's stock in HCA. Not too long after this action, HCA, Inc. stock declined 9% in value in a single day.

     CREW's first allegation—that Frist violated FEC rules—is rather clear cut. The FEC found a rules violation to have occurred and Frist 2000, Inc. had to pay an $11,000 conciliation civil penalty. The case against Frist himself and Frist 2000, Inc.'s former treasurer and vice-treasurer was dismissed. Frist's alleged insider trading is also clear cut, but not in the way CREW would like it to be. Frist claimed from the start of the investigation that his action had been to avoid a conflict of interest when he advanced legislation affecting healthcare, and after an eighteen month investigation Frist was completely exonerated. His exoneration in this investigation was not enough to save his political career, and a man who had been thought to be a leading Republican presidential candidate was forced out of public life.

Senator Rick Santorum (R-PA):

     Rick Santorum was elected to the senate in 1995 and served until 2007 and in the House of Representatives from 1991 to 1995. During his time in office Santorum served on the Senate Armed Services Committee and was the third ranking Republican in the senate, the first Pennsylvanian to hold such a prominent position since the 1970s. Santorum was a staunch conservative throughout his career in both houses of congress, routinely receiving high ratings from the American Conservative Union, Concerned Women for America, National Right to Life, and other conservative groups. Although Santorum served on the Armed Services Committee, he was best known for his strong conservative stand on social issues and his defense of the traditional family, attracting the ire of pro-homosexual marriage and pro-abortion activists.

     In 2006 Santorum faced a tough challenge from Bob Casey, the son of the former Pennsylvania governor of the same name. Santorum trailed by fifteen points or more throughout the campaign and wasn't helped by CREW's report.

     CREW accused Santorum of having his children enroll in a cyber-school paid for by the Penn Hills school district from 2001 to 2005 while he and his family lived in Virginia. Although Santorum was a legal resident of the Penn Hills district, CREW (and the district) alleged that he willfully ignored the further requirement that children enrolled in the cyber-school not only had to be legal residents of the district but also had to spend most of their time there. CREW claimed that Santorum's children had cost the district $72,000 while attending the cyber-school.

     CREW also produced a long list of legislative decisions which they believed to be linked to campaign contributions. Among these was Santorum's attempt to break the National Weather Service's government-funded near-monopoly on the dissemination of weather information. CREW points to donations from the founder of AccuWeather, a private weather service, as bribes. CREW also points to donations from the U.S. Tobacco Corporation's political action committee, U.S. Team, after Santorum opposed the regulation of tobacco companies, Santorum's support of equal Medicare reimbursement for hospitals in Puerto Rico, which was followed by donations from various hospitals in Puerto Rico, and Santorum's support of a cutting edge coal-to-diesel plant in Schuylkill County, Pennsylvania, which was followed by large donations from the owner of the company that would build the plant (Waste Management and Processes, Inc) and his relatives.

     CREW's charge that Santorum willfully ignored residency requirements is flawed on two counts. First, CREW grossly overestimated the cost to Pennsylvania taxpayers. CREW's estimate is at the top of the spectrum of estimates, which range from $34,000 to $72,000. Even given the high cost CREW posits, the cost per student over the five years was actually only $3,600 per year—well under the national average of $8,000 to $9,000 per student per year. More importantly, in fact, the requirements for the cyber-school left it unclear whether all that was required was legal residency—in essence property taxes supporting the school district—or whether actual residency was required as well. When informed of the school district's interpretation of the matter (that actual residency was required) Santorum immediately removed his children and resumed homeschooling them. Incidentally, the ambiguity was cleared in Santorum's favor in 2005 when the residency requirement was explicitly changed to include children of elected officials who did not spend most of their time in the district but were legal residents.

     CREW's allegations of taking bribes are far less believable—so little evidence was provided, in fact, that no investigation was ever conducted. In every case there is nothing to suggest the donations were not driven by a desire on the part of the donor to help a politician who stood up for them. It is the natural course of things that people will support those in government who support them—that fact alone is not evidence of a bribe.

     To summarize, Senator Burns was cleared of CREW's charges when investigated, although some were not investigated at all because sufficient evidence was not provided to support them. Senator Frist's 2000 campaign was found to have violated FEC rules and required to pay an $11,000 conciliation civil penalty, but Frist was completely exonerated on the charge of insider trading. Senator Santorum was exonerated in having enrolled his kids in the Western Pennsylvania Cyber School, and the evidence of his having allowed campaign contributions to influence his decisions was deemed insufficient to pursue an investigation.


In short, CREW took aim at three conservative senators in a move that was partisan politics at its worst. It wasn't an attack based on issues or substance, it was nothing less than libelous character assassination. The political affiliations of CREW's staff and the politicians named cast doubt on the veracity of its report, and an examination of the facts does nothing but confirm those doubts

     Science: the word itself conjures up a plethora of images ranging from wild-eyed geniuses in lab coats scribbling esoteric ramblings in disorderly notebooks to the wild, rough world of field disciplines such as geology and biology. Science has brought incredible benefits to the world and has become firmly entrenched as the unquestioned best source of truth about the material world. At the same time, perhaps even as a result of this success, the world today has developed a particularly absurd view of science. It is held with an almost religious fervor by many to be the only method of determining truth. The vast majority of scientists, and even, I would guess, a very large percentage of the population, holds to this view, either explicitly or implicitly. While this view seems quite reasonable—science, after all, is the process of applying reason to learn about the world—it holds a fatal flaw. Science, by its very nature, can only address the physical realm. It cannot provide answers about either the existence or nature of the metaphysical realm. It cannot address any question that does not have as its answer some natural process, and those who cling to science alone for truth must simply posit, without any form of proof, that no such question can exist in the real world.

     The flaw lies in the very foundations of science. It was conceived as a method for acquiring information about the material world, a task for which it is a very effective tool. For any phenomenon which can be explained purely through natural causes science is unrivaled. In the event, however, that it is faced with phenomena of supernatural origins science can produce no answer. This results from the fact that science begins by excluding the supernatural. Pure science “cannot allow a divine foot in the door,” as Richard Lewontin put it. In essence it asks “what natural causes can one find for this phenomenon?” In asking that question alone it excludes the divine and places facts and empiricism at the feet of philosophy and a priori presuppositions—the very thing it seeks to avoid. Science is thus inextricably intertwined with philosophy and cannot produce a coherent worldview on its own, however much research and effort one puts into into it.

     Still, most of the time science produces a reasonable answer. It gave us, as many materialists like to point out, the electric light, the airplane, space travel, and much more. It is true that most of the time the world behaves in a predictable, completely ordinary manner (this is actually an excellent argument for the Judeo-Christian worldview, incidentally) and in these cases science is our best method of finding an answer. If something out of the ordinary has occurred science will, however, produce a nonsensical answer. Nowhere is this fact more evident than in the subject of origins, an area that cries out that something profoundly extraordinary has taken place. In this realm science cannot produce a reasonable answer. Take cosmic evolution: each step is more improbable than the last, beginning with a quantum fluctuation in nothing that produced everything. Moving further in the process, excellent work has been done analyzing faster than light expansion and subsequent localized contraction, and as of yet no reason for or driving force behind either posited occurrence has been found. Taken as a whole, the hypothesis is disturbingly close to a statistical impossibility and, in fact, is arguably completely impossible. It is a perfect example of the futile flailing of science divorced from all other forms of seeking truth.
     Science is nonetheless the best method we have of learning about the physical world. Divested of this, our best recourse, will we be forced to return to a time when foolish superstition driven by fear suppressed understanding? Certainly not! Indeed, the fallacy that led many in the past to attempt to explain the world around them solely through superstition is, in many ways, the same that leads many today to attempt to explain everything through science: the search for one process that can answer any question, an ultimate panacea. Instead, we should remember that the search for truth is bigger than any one method and allow ourselves to consider every possibility. It is not only the best way to truly understand the world around us, it is integral to our unique purpose as humans to seek and find truth wherever it can be found.

Newer Posts Home